open import Cat.Diagram.Limit.Equaliser open import Cat.Diagram.Limit.Pullback open import Cat.Instances.Shape.Cospan open import Cat.Diagram.Limit.Product open import Cat.Diagram.Limit.Base open import Cat.Instances.Discrete open import Cat.Diagram.Equaliser open import Cat.Diagram.Pullback open import Cat.Diagram.Terminal open import Cat.Diagram.Product open import Cat.Instances.Lift open import Cat.Prelude open import Cat.Thin open import Data.Bool import Cat.Reasoning as Cat module Cat.Diagram.Limit.Finite where
Finitely Complete Categories🔗
A category is said to be finitely complete if it admits limits for every diagram with a finite shape. While this condition might sound very strong, and thus that it would be hard to come by, it turns out we can get away with only the following common shapes of limits:
- A terminal object (limit over the empty diagram)
- Binary products (limits over diagrams of the form , that is, two points)
- Binary equalisers (limits over diagrams of the form )
- Binary pullbacks (limits over diagrams of the form )
In reality, the list above has some redundancy. Since we can build products out of pullbacks and a terminal object, and conversely we can build pullbacks out of products and equalisers, either of the following subsets suffices:
- A terminal object, binary products, binary equalisers;
- A terminal object and binary pullbacks.
For proving that a thin category is finitely complete, given that equalisers are trivial and pullbacks coincide with products, it suffices to give a terminal object and binary products.
record Finitely-complete : Type (ℓ ⊔ ℓ') where field terminal : Terminal C products : ∀ A B → Product C A B equalisers : ∀ {A B} (f g : Hom A B) → Equaliser C f g pullbacks : ∀ {A B X} (f : Hom A X) (g : Hom B X) → Pullback C f g Eq : ∀ {A B} (f g : Hom A B) → Ob Eq f g = equalisers f g .Equaliser.apex Pb : ∀ {A B C} (f : Hom A C) (g : Hom B C) → Ob Pb f g = pullbacks f g .Pullback.apex module Cart = Cartesian C products open Cart using (_⊗_) public open Finitely-complete
With equalisers🔗
We now prove that having products and equalisers suffices to have all pullbacks; Thus a terminal object, binary products and binary equalisers suffice for finite completeness.
The main result is as follows: Let be a (the) product of and , with its projections called and . Letting be a cospan, if the composites and have an equaliser , then the square
is a pullback. Now, that description is almost entirely abstract-nonsensical, because (for generality) we do not use any “canonical” products or equalisers . If we work slightly more concretely, then this can be read as building the pullback as the largest subobject of where agree. In particular, the pullback we want is the object in the commutative diagram below.
product-equaliser→pullback : ∀ {E P X Y Z} {p1 : Hom P X} {p2 : Hom P Y} {f : Hom X Z} {g : Hom Y Z} {e : Hom E P} → is-product C p1 p2 → is-equaliser C (f ∘ p1) (g ∘ p2) e → is-pullback C (p1 ∘ e) f (p2 ∘ e) g product-equaliser→pullback {p1 = p1} {p2} {f} {g} {e} prod eq = pb where open is-pullback module eq = is-equaliser eq module pr = is-product prod pb : is-pullback C _ _ _ _ pb .square = assoc _ _ _ ∙ eq.equal ∙ sym (assoc _ _ _)
To show that this object really is a pullback of and , note that we can factor any pair of arrows and through the Cartesian product , and use the universal property of equalisers to factor that as a unique arrow .
pb .limiting {p₁' = p₁'} {p₂' = p₂'} p = eq.limiting {e′ = pr.⟨ p₁' , p₂' ⟩pr.} ( (f ∘ p1) ∘ pr.⟨ p₁' , p₂' ⟩pr. ≡⟨ pullr pr.π₁∘factor ⟩≡ f ∘ p₁' ≡⟨ p ⟩≡ g ∘ p₂' ≡˘⟨ pullr pr.π₂∘factor ⟩≡˘ (g ∘ p2) ∘ pr.⟨ p₁' , p₂' ⟩pr. ∎ ) pb .p₁∘limiting = pullr eq.universal ∙ pr.π₁∘factor pb .p₂∘limiting = pullr eq.universal ∙ pr.π₂∘factor pb .unique p q = eq.unique (sym (pr.unique _ (assoc _ _ _ ∙ p) (assoc _ _ _ ∙ q)))
Hence, assuming that a category has a terminal object, binary products and binary equalisers means it also admits pullbacks.
with-equalisers : Terminal C → (∀ A B → Product C A B) → (∀ {A B} (f g : Hom A B) → Equaliser C f g) → Finitely-complete with-equalisers top prod equ .terminal = top with-equalisers top prod equ .products = prod with-equalisers top prod equ .equalisers = equ with-equalisers top prod equ .pullbacks {A} {B} {X} f g = record { has-is-pb = product-equaliser→pullback Prod.has-is-product Equ.has-is-eq } where module Prod = Product (prod A B) module Equ = Equaliser (equ (f ∘ Prod.π₁) (g ∘ Prod.π₂))
With pullbacks🔗
We’ll now prove the converse: That a terminal object and pullbacks implies having all products, and all equalisers. We’ll start with the products, since those are simpler. Observe that we can complete a product diagram (like the one on the left) to a pullback diagram (like the one on the right) by adding in the unique arrows into the terminal object .
terminal-pullback→product : ∀ {P X Y T} {p1 : Hom P X} {p2 : Hom P Y} {f : Hom X T} {g : Hom Y T} → is-terminal C T → is-pullback C p1 f p2 g → is-product C p1 p2 terminal-pullback→product {p1 = p1} {p2} {f} {g} term pb = prod where
module Pb = is-pullback pb prod : is-product C p1 p2 prod .is-product.⟨_,_⟩ p1' p2' = Pb.limiting {p₁' = p1'} {p₂' = p2'} (is-contr→is-prop (term _) _ _) prod .is-product.π₁∘factor = Pb.p₁∘limiting prod .is-product.π₂∘factor = Pb.p₂∘limiting prod .is-product.unique other p q = Pb.unique p q with-pullbacks : Terminal C → (∀ {A B X} (f : Hom A X) (g : Hom B X) → Pullback C f g) → Finitely-complete with-pullbacks top pb = fc where module top = Terminal top mkprod : ∀ A B → Product C A B mkprod A B = record { has-is-product = terminal-pullback→product top.has⊤ pb′ } where pb′ = pb (top.has⊤ A .centre) (top.has⊤ B .centre) .Pullback.has-is-pb mkeq : ∀ {A B} (f g : Hom A B) → Equaliser C f g mkeq {A = A} {B} f g = eq where
For equalisers, the situation is a bit more complicated. Recall that, by analogy with the case in Set, we can consider the equaliser to be the solution set of , for some . We can consider the two sides of this equation as a single map ; The equation is solved where this pairing map equals some . We can thus build equalisers by pulling back along the diagonal map:
The actual equaliser map is the top, horizontal face (what the code calls Pb.p₂), so we must show that, composed with this map, and become equal. Here’s where we use the fact that pullback squares, well, commute: We know that is , and that (since the square above is a pullback).
But both projections out of are equal, so we can apply commutativity of the square above again to conclude that .
eq : Equaliser C f g eq .apex = Pb.apex eq .equ = Pb.p₂ eq .has-is-eq .equal = f ∘ Pb.p₂ ≡˘⟨ pulll Bb.π₁∘factor ⟩≡˘ Bb.π₁ ∘ ⟨f,g⟩ ∘ Pb.p₂ ≡⟨ ap (Bb.π₁ ∘_) (sym Pb.square) ⟩≡ Bb.π₁ ∘ ⟨id,id⟩ ∘ Pb.p₁ ≡⟨ pulll Bb.π₁∘factor ∙ sym (pulll Bb.π₂∘factor) ⟩≡ Bb.π₂ ∘ ⟨id,id⟩ ∘ Pb.p₁ ≡⟨ ap (Bb.π₂ ∘_) Pb.square ⟩≡ Bb.π₂ ∘ ⟨f,g⟩ ∘ Pb.p₂ ≡⟨ pulll Bb.π₂∘factor ⟩≡ g ∘ Pb.p₂ ∎
We must now show that if is another map which equalises and , then it fits into a commutative diagram like the one below, so that we may conclude the dashed arrow exists and is unique.
A bit of boring limit-chasing lets us conclude that this diagram does commute, hence the dashed arrow does exist (uniquely!), so that the top face in our pullback diagram is indeed the equaliser of and .
eq .has-is-eq .limiting {e′ = e′} p = Pb.limiting (Bb.unique₂ refl refl (sym p1) (sym p2)) where p1 : Bb.π₁ ∘ ⟨id,id⟩ ∘ f ∘ e′ ≡ Bb.π₁ ∘ ⟨f,g⟩ ∘ e′ p1 = Bb.π₁ ∘ ⟨id,id⟩ ∘ f ∘ e′ ≡⟨ cancell Bb.π₁∘factor ⟩≡ f ∘ e′ ≡˘⟨ pulll Bb.π₁∘factor ⟩≡˘ Bb.π₁ ∘ ⟨f,g⟩ ∘ e′ ∎ p2 : Bb.π₂ ∘ ⟨id,id⟩ ∘ f ∘ e′ ≡ Bb.π₂ ∘ ⟨f,g⟩ ∘ e′ p2 = Bb.π₂ ∘ ⟨id,id⟩ ∘ f ∘ e′ ≡⟨ cancell Bb.π₂∘factor ⟩≡ f ∘ e′ ≡⟨ p ⟩≡ g ∘ e′ ≡˘⟨ pulll Bb.π₂∘factor ⟩≡˘ Bb.π₂ ∘ ⟨f,g⟩ ∘ e′ ∎ eq .has-is-eq .universal = Pb.p₂∘limiting eq .has-is-eq .unique {F} {e′ = e′} {lim' = lim'} e′=p₂∘l = Pb.unique path (sym e′=p₂∘l) where path : Pb.p₁ ∘ lim' ≡ f ∘ e′ path = Pb.p₁ ∘ lim' ≡⟨ insertl Bb.π₁∘factor ⟩≡ Bb.π₁ ∘ ⟨id,id⟩ ∘ Pb.p₁ ∘ lim' ≡⟨ ap (Bb.π₁ ∘_) (extendl Pb.square) ⟩≡ Bb.π₁ ∘ ⟨f,g⟩ ∘ Pb.p₂ ∘ lim' ≡⟨ ap (Bb.π₁ ∘_) (ap (⟨f,g⟩ ∘_) (sym e′=p₂∘l)) ⟩≡ Bb.π₁ ∘ ⟨f,g⟩ ∘ e′ ≡⟨ pulll Bb.π₁∘factor ⟩≡ f ∘ e′ ∎
Putting it all together into a record we get our proof of finite completeness:
fc : Finitely-complete fc .terminal = top fc .products = mkprod fc .equalisers = mkeq fc .pullbacks = pb
Thinly🔗
Assuming that is a thin category, it suffices to give constructions of products (i.e. meets) and a terminal object (i.e. a top element). In this sense, finitely complete thin categories correspond to bounded meet semilattices.
with-top-and-meets : is-thin C → Terminal C → (∀ A B → Product C A B) → Finitely-complete with-top-and-meets thin top meets = fc where open Pullback module Thin = is-thin thin fc : Finitely-complete fc .terminal = top fc .products = meets
For equalisers, note that since any pair of parallel arrows was assumed to be equal (since the category is thin), we can take the domain of the equaliser to be and the equalising arrow to be .
fc .equalisers {A} {B} f g = equalise where open Equaliser open is-equaliser equalise : Equaliser C _ _ equalise .apex = A equalise .equ = id equalise .has-is-eq .equal = Thin.Hom-is-prop _ _ _ _ equalise .has-is-eq .limiting {e′ = e′} p = e′ equalise .has-is-eq .universal = idl _ equalise .has-is-eq .unique p = Thin.Hom-is-prop _ _ _ _
For pullbacks, we note that since the maps into the object are trivial, they do not factor into the definition. The square automatically commutes independently of them, because, again, the category is thin. Therefore, we can simply take as the definition of pullback.
fc .pullbacks {A} {B} f g = pb where open Pullback open is-pullback module P = Product (meets A B) pb : Pullback C _ _ pb .apex = P.apex pb .p₁ = P.π₁ pb .p₂ = P.π₂ pb .has-is-pb .square = Thin.Hom-is-prop _ _ _ _ pb .has-is-pb .limiting {p₁' = p₁′} {p₂' = p₂′} p = P.⟨ p₁′ , p₂′ ⟩P. pb .has-is-pb .p₁∘limiting = P.π₁∘factor pb .has-is-pb .p₂∘limiting = P.π₂∘factor pb .has-is-pb .unique _ _ = Thin.Hom-is-prop _ _ _ _
Lex functors🔗
A functor is said to be left exact, abbreviated lex, when it preserves finite limits. These functors aren’t called “finite-limit-preserving functors” by historical accident, and for brevity. By the characterisations above, it suffices for a functor to preserve the terminal object and pullbacks.
record is-lex (F : Functor C D) : Type (o ⊔ ℓ ⊔ o′ ⊔ ℓ′) where private module F = Functor F field pres-⊤ : ∀ {T} → is-terminal C T → is-terminal D (F.₀ T) pres-pullback : ∀ {P X Y Z} {p1 : C.Hom P X} {p2 : C.Hom P Y} {f : C.Hom X Z} {g : C.Hom Y Z} → is-pullback C p1 f p2 g → is-pullback D (F.₁ p1) (F.₁ f) (F.₁ p2) (F.₁ g)
Since (if a terminal object exists), products can be identified with pullbacks , if has a terminal object, then a lex functor also preserves products.
pres-product : ∀ {P A B T} {p1 : C.Hom P A} {p2 : C.Hom P B} → is-terminal C T → is-product C p1 p2 → is-product D (F.₁ p1) (F.₁ p2) pres-product term pr = terminal-pullback→product D (pres-⊤ term) (pres-pullback {f = term _ .centre} {g = term _ .centre} (product→terminal-pullback C term pr))