open import Algebra.Group.Cat.FinitelyComplete open import Algebra.Group.Cat.Base open import Algebra.Prelude open import Algebra.Group open import Cat.Diagram.Equaliser.Kernel open import Data.Power module Algebra.Group.Subgroup where
Subgroups🔗
A subgroup of a group is a monomorphism , that is, an object of the poset of subobjects . Since group homomorphisms are injective exactly when their underlying function is an embedding, we can alternatively describe this as a condition on a predicate .
Subgroup : Group ℓ → Type (lsuc ℓ) Subgroup {ℓ = ℓ} G = Precategory.Ob (Subobj (Groups ℓ) G)
A proposition of a group represents a subgroup if it contains the group unit, is closed under multiplication, and is closed under inverses.
record represents-subgroup (G : Group ℓ) (H : ℙ (G .fst)) : Type ℓ where open Group-on (G .snd) field has-unit : unit ∈ H has-⋆ : ∀ {x y} → x ∈ H → y ∈ H → (x ⋆ y) ∈ H has-inv : ∀ {x} → x ∈ H → x ⁻¹ ∈ H
If represents a subgroup, then its total space inherits a group structure from , and the first projection is a group homormophism.
rep-subgroup→group-on : (H : ℙ (G .fst)) → represents-subgroup G H → Group-on (Σ[ x ∈ G .fst ] x ∈ H) rep-subgroup→group-on {G = G} H sg = make-group (Σ-is-hlevel 2 has-is-set λ x → is-prop→is-set (H x .is-tr)) (unit , has-unit) (λ { (x , xin) (y , yin) → x ⋆ y , has-⋆ xin yin} ) (λ { (x , xin) → (x ⁻¹ , has-inv xin) }) (λ x y z → Σ-prop-path (λ x → H x .is-tr) (sym associative)) (λ x → Σ-prop-path (λ x → H x .is-tr) inversel) (λ x → Σ-prop-path (λ x → H x .is-tr) inverser) (λ x → Σ-prop-path (λ x → H x .is-tr) idl) where open Group-on (G .snd) open represents-subgroup sg predicate→subgroup : (H : ℙ (G .fst)) → represents-subgroup G H → Subgroup G predicate→subgroup {G = G} H p = cut map , ism where map : Groups.Hom (Σ (∣_∣ ⊙ H) , rep-subgroup→group-on H p) G map .fst = fst map .snd .Group-hom.pres-⋆ x y = refl ism : Groups.is-monic map ism g h p = Forget-is-faithful (embedding→monic (Subset-proj-embedding (is-tr ⊙ H)) (fst g) (fst h) (ap fst p))
Kernels and Images🔗
To a group homomorphism we can associate two canonical subgroups, one of and one of : ’s image, written , is the subgroup of “reachable by mapping through ”, and ’s kernel, written , is the subgroup of which sends to the unit.
The kernel can be cheapily described as a limit: It is the equaliser of and the zero morphism — which, recall, is the unique map which breaks down as .
module _ {ℓ} where open Canonical-kernels (Groups ℓ) ∅ᴳ Groups-equalisers public Ker-subgroup : ∀ {A B : Group ℓ} → Groups.Hom A B → Subgroup A Ker-subgroup f = cut kernel , Groups.is-equaliser→is-monic _ has-is-kernel where open Kernel (Ker f)
Every group homomorphism has an image , defined by equipping its set-theoretic image with a group structure inherited from . More concretely, we can describe the elements of as the “mere fibres” of : They consist of a point , together with (the truncation of) a fibre of over . We multiply (in the fibre over ) with (in the fibre over ), giving the element in the fibre over .
For reasons that will become clear later, we denote the image of , when regarded as its own group, by , and reserve the notation for that group regarded as a subgroup of .
The construction of a group structure on is unsurprising, so we leave it in this <details>
tag for the curious reader.
T : Type ℓ T = image (f .fst) A/ker[_] : Group ℓ A/ker[_] = T , grp where unit : T unit = B.unit , inc (A.unit , f.pres-id) inv : T → T inv (x , p) = x B.⁻¹ , ∥-∥-map (λ { (y , p) → y A.⁻¹ , f.pres-inv ∙ ap B._⁻¹ p }) p mul : T → T → T mul (x , xp) (y , yp) = x B.⋆ y , ∥-∥-elim₂ (λ _ _ → squash) (λ { (x* , xp) (y* , yp) → inc (x* A.⋆ y* , f.pres-⋆ _ _ ∙ ap₂ B._⋆_ xp yp) }) xp yp grp : Group-on T grp = make-group Tset unit mul inv (λ x y z → Tpath (sym B.associative)) (λ x → Tpath B.inversel) (λ x → Tpath B.inverser) λ x → Tpath B.idl
That the canonical inclusion map deserves the name “image” comes from breaking down as a (regular) epimorphism into (written A→im), followed by that map:
A→im : Groups.Hom A A/ker[_] A→im .fst x = f .fst x , inc (x , refl) A→im .snd .Group-hom.pres-⋆ x y = Tpath (f.pres-⋆ _ _) im→B : Groups.Hom A/ker[_] B im→B .fst (b , _) = b im→B .snd .Group-hom.pres-⋆ x y = refl
When this monomorphism is taken as primary, we refer to as .
Im[_] : Subgroup B Im[_] = cut im→B , im↪B where im↪B : Groups.is-monic im→B im↪B = injective-group-hom im→B Tpath
The reason for denoting the set-theoretic image of (which is a subobject of , equipped with ’s group operation) by is the first isomorphism theorem (though we phrase it more categorically): The image of serves as a quotient for (the congruence generated by) .
Note: In more classical texts, the first isomorphism theorem is phrased in terms of two pre-existing objects (defined as the set of cosets of regarded as a subgroup) and (defined as above). Here we have opted for a more categorical phrasing of that theorem: We know what the universal property of is — namely that it is a specific colimit — so the specific construction used to implement it does not matter.
1st-iso-theorem : Groups.is-coequaliser (Groups.Zero.zero→ ∅ᴳ) Kerf.kernel A→im 1st-iso-theorem = coeq where open Groups open is-coequaliser module Ak = Group-on (A/ker[_] .snd)
More specifically, in a diagram like the one below, the indicated dotted arrow always exists and is unique, witnessing that the map is a coequaliser (hence that it is a regular epi, as we mentioned above).
The condition placed on is that ; This means that it, like , sends everything in to zero (this is the defining property of ). Note that in the code below we do not elide the zero composite .
elim : ∀ {F} {e' : Groups.Hom A F} (p : e' Groups.∘ Zero.zero→ ∅ᴳ ≡ e' Groups.∘ Kerf.kernel) → ∀ {x} → ∥ fibre (f .fst) x ∥ → _ elim {F = F} {e' = e' , gh} p {x} = ∥-∥-rec-set (e' ⊙ fst) const (F .snd .Group-on.has-is-set) where abstract module e' = Group-hom gh module F = Group-on (F .snd)
To eliminate from under a [propositional truncation], we must prove that the map is constant when thought of as a map ; In other words, it means that is “independent of the choice of representative”. This follows from algebraic manipulation of group homomorphisms + the assumed identity ;
const′ : ∀ (x y : fibre (f .fst) x) → e' (x .fst) F.— e' (y .fst) ≡ F.unit const′ (y , q) (z , r) = e' y F.— e' z ≡˘⟨ e'.pres-diff ⟩≡˘ e' (y A.— z) ≡⟨ happly (sym (ap fst p)) (y A.— z , aux) ⟩≡ e' A.unit ≡⟨ e'.pres-id ⟩≡ F.unit ∎ where
This assumption allows us to reduce “show that is constant on a specific subset” to “show that when ”; But that’s just algebra, hence uninteresting:
aux : f .fst (y A.— z) ≡ B.unit aux = f .fst (y A.— z) ≡⟨ f.pres-diff ⟩≡ f .fst y B.— f .fst z ≡⟨ ap₂ B._—_ q r ⟩≡ x B.— x ≡⟨ B.inverser ⟩≡ B.unit ∎ const : ∀ (x y : fibre (f .fst) x) → (e' (x .fst)) ≡ (e' (y .fst)) const a b = F.zero-diff (const′ a b)
The rest of the construction is almost tautological: By definition, if , then , so the quotient map does indeed coequalise and . As a final word on the rest of the construction, most of it is applying induction (∥-∥-elim and friends) so that our colimiting map elim will compute.
coeq : is-coequaliser _ _ A→im coeq .coequal = Forget-is-faithful (funext path) where path : (x : Kerf.ker .fst) → A→im .fst A.unit ≡ A→im .fst (x .fst) path (x* , p) = Tpath (f.pres-id ∙ sym p) coeq .coequalise {F = F} {e′ = e'} p = gh where module F = Group-on (F .snd) module e' = Group-hom (e' .snd) gh : Groups.Hom _ _ gh .fst (x , t) = elim {e' = e'} p t gh .snd .Group-hom.pres-⋆ (x , q) (y , r) = ∥-∥-elim₂ {P = λ q r → elim p (((x , q) Ak.⋆ (y , r)) .snd) ≡ elim p q F.⋆ elim p r} (λ _ _ → F.has-is-set _ _) (λ x y → e'.pres-⋆ _ _) q r coeq .universal = Forget-is-faithful refl coeq .unique {F} {p = p} {colim = colim} prf = Forget-is-faithful (funext path) where abstract module F = Group-on (F .snd) path : ∀ x → colim .fst x ≡ elim p (x .snd) path (x , t) = ∥-∥-elim {P = λ q → colim .fst (x , q) ≡ elim p q} (λ _ → F.has-is-set _ _) (λ { (f , fp) → ap (colim .fst) (Σ-prop-path (λ _ → squash) (sym fp)) ∙ sym (happly (ap fst prf) f) }) t
Representing kernels🔗
If an evil wizard kidnaps your significant others and demands that you find out whether a predicate is a kernel, how would you go about doing it? Well, I should point out that no matter how evil the wizard is, they are still human: The predicate definitely represents a subgroup, in the sense introduced above — so there’s definitely a group homomorphism . All we need to figure out is whether there exists a group and a map , such that as subgroups of .
We begin by assuming that we have a kernel and investigating some properties that the fibres of its inclusion have. Of course, the fibre over is inhabited, and they are closed under multiplication and inverses, though we shall not make note of that here).
module _ {ℓ} {A B : Group ℓ} (f : Groups.Hom A B) where private module Ker[f] = Kernel (Ker f) module f = Group-hom (f .snd) module A = Group-on (A .snd) module B = Group-on (B .snd) kerf : Ker[f].ker .fst → A .fst kerf = Ker[f].kernel .fst has-zero : fibre kerf A.unit has-zero = (A.unit , f.pres-id) , refl has-⋆ : ∀ {x y} → fibre kerf x → fibre kerf y → fibre kerf (x A.⋆ y) has-⋆ ((a , p) , q) ((b , r) , s) = (a A.⋆ b , f.pres-⋆ _ _ ·· ap₂ B._⋆_ p r ·· B.idl) , ap₂ A._⋆_ q s
It turns out that is also closed under conjugation by elements of the enveloping group, in that if (quickly switching to “multiplicative” notation for the unit), then must be as well: for we have .
has-conjugate : ∀ {x y} → fibre kerf x → fibre kerf (y A.⋆ x A.⋆ y A.⁻¹) has-conjugate {x} {y} ((a , p) , q) = (_ , path) , refl where path = f .fst (y A.⋆ (x A.— y)) ≡⟨ ap (f .fst) A.associative ⟩≡ f .fst ((y A.⋆ x) A.— y) ≡⟨ f.pres-diff ⟩≡ f .fst (y A.⋆ x) B.— f .fst y ≡⟨ ap (B._⋆ _) (f.pres-⋆ y x) ⟩≡ (f .fst y B.⋆ f .fst x) B.— f .fst y ≡⟨ ap (B._⋆ _) (ap (_ B.⋆_) (ap (f .fst) (sym q) ∙ p) ∙ B.idr) ⟩≡ f .fst y B.— f .fst y ≡˘⟨ f.pres-diff ⟩≡˘ f .fst (y A.— y) ≡⟨ ap (f .fst) A.inverser ∙ f.pres-id ⟩≡ B.unit ∎
It turns out that this last property is enough to pick out exactly the kernels amongst the representations of subgroups: If is closed under conjugation, then generates an equivalence relation on the set underlying (namely, ), and equip the quotient of this equivalence relation with a group structure. The kernel of the quotient map is then . We call a predicate representing a kernel a normal subgroup, and we denote this in shorthand by .
record normal-subgroup (G : Group ℓ) (H : ℙ (G .fst)) : Type ℓ where open Group-on (G .snd) field has-rep : represents-subgroup G H has-conjugate : ∀ {x y} → x ∈ H → (y ⋆ x ⋆ y ⁻¹) ∈ H has-conjugatel : ∀ {x y} → y ∈ H → ((x ⋆ y) ⋆ x ⁻¹) ∈ H has-conjugatel yin = subst (_∈ H) associative (has-conjugate yin) has-comm : ∀ {x y} → (x ⋆ y) ∈ H → (y ⋆ x) ∈ H has-comm {x = x} {y} ∈ = subst (_∈ H) p (has-conjugate ∈) where p = x ⁻¹ ⋆ (x ⋆ y) ⋆ x ⁻¹ ⁻¹ ≡⟨ ap₂ _⋆_ refl (sym associative) ∙ (λ i → x ⁻¹ ⋆ x ⋆ y ⋆ inv-inv {x = x} i) ⟩≡ x ⁻¹ ⋆ x ⋆ y ⋆ x ≡⟨ associative ⟩≡ (x ⁻¹ ⋆ x) ⋆ y ⋆ x ≡⟨ ap₂ _⋆_ inversel refl ∙ idl ⟩≡ y ⋆ x ∎ open represents-subgroup has-rep public
So, suppose we have a normal subgroup . We define the underlying type of the quotient to be the quotient of the relation ; It can be equipped with a group operation inherited from , but this is incredibly tedious to do.
G/H : Type _ G/H = G0 / rel op : G/H → G/H → G/H op = Quot-op₂ rel-refl rel-refl _⋆_ (λ w x y z a b → rem₃ y z w x b a) where
To prove that the group operation _⋆_ descends to the quotient, we prove that it takes related inputs to related outputs — a characterisation of binary operations on quotients we can invoke since the relation we’re quotienting by is reflexive. It suffices to show that whenever and are both in , which is a tedious but straightforward calculation:
module _ (w x y z : G0) (w-x∈ : (w ⋆ inv x) ∈ H) (y-z∈ : (y ⋆ inv z) ∈ H) where abstract rem₁ : ((w — x) ⋆ (inv z ⋆ y)) ∈ H rem₁ = has-⋆ w-x∈ (has-comm y-z∈) rem₂ : ((w ⋆ (inv x — z)) ⋆ y) ∈ H rem₂ = subst (_∈ H) (associative ∙ ap (_⋆ y) (sym associative)) rem₁ rem₃ : ((y ⋆ w) — (z ⋆ x)) ∈ H rem₃ = subst (_∈ H) (associative ∙ ap₂ _⋆_ refl (sym inv-comm)) (has-comm rem₂)
To define inverses on the quotient, it suffices to show that whenever , we also have .
inverse : G/H → G/H inverse = Coeq-rec squash (λ x → inc (inv x)) λ { (x , y , r) → quot (p x y r) } where abstract p : ∀ x y → (x — y) ∈ H → (inv x — inv y) ∈ H p x y r = has-comm (subst (_∈ H) inv-comm (has-inv r))
Even after this tedious algebra, it still remains to show that the operation is associative and has inverses. Fortunately, since equality in a group is a proposition, these follow from the group axioms on rather directly:
Group-on-G/H : Group-on G/H Group-on-G/H = make-group squash (inc unit) op inverse (Coeq-elim-prop₃ (λ _ _ _ → squash _ _) λ x y z i → inc (associative {x = x} {y} {z} (~ i))) (Coeq-elim-prop (λ _ → squash _ _) λ x i → inc (inversel {x = x} i)) (Coeq-elim-prop (λ _ → squash _ _) λ x i → inc (inverser {x = x} i)) (Coeq-elim-prop (λ _ → squash _ _) λ x i → inc (idl {x = x} i)) _/ᴳ_ : Group _ _/ᴳ_ = G/H , Group-on-G/H incl : Groups.Hom Grp _/ᴳ_ incl .fst = inc incl .snd .Group-hom.pres-⋆ x y = refl
Before we show that the kernel of the quotient map is isomorphic to the subgroup we started with (and indeed, that this isomorphism commutes with the respective, so that they determine the same subobject of ), we must show that the relation is an equivalence relation; We can then appeal to effectivity of quotients to conclude that, if , then .
private rel-sym : ∀ {x y} → rel x y → rel y x rel-sym h = subst (_∈ H) (inv-comm ∙ ap (_⋆ _) inv-inv) (has-inv h) rel-trans : ∀ {x y z} → rel x y → rel y z → rel x z rel-trans {x} {y} {z} h g = subst (_∈ H) p (has-⋆ h g) where p = (x — y) ⋆ (y — z) ≡˘⟨ associative ⟩≡˘ x ⋆ (y ⁻¹ ⋆ (y — z)) ≡⟨ ap (x ⋆_) associative ⟩≡ x ⋆ ((y ⁻¹ ⋆ y) — z) ≡⟨ ap (x ⋆_) (ap (_⋆ _) inversel ∙ idl) ⟩≡ x — z ∎ /ᴳ-effective : ∀ {x y} → Path G/H (inc x) (inc y) → rel x y /ᴳ-effective = equiv→inverse (effective (λ _ _ → H _ .is-tr) (rel-refl _) rel-trans rel-sym)
The two halves of the isomorphism are now very straightforward to define: If we have , then by effectivity, and by the group laws. Conversely, if , then , thus they are identified in the quotient. Thus, the predicate recovers the subgroup ; And (the total space of) that predicate is exactly the kernel of !
Ker[incl]≅H-group : Ker[incl].ker Groups.≅ H-g Ker[incl]≅H-group = Groups.make-iso to from il ir where to : Groups.Hom _ _ to .fst (x , p) = x , subst (_∈ H) (ap (_ ⋆_) inv-unit ∙ idr) x-0∈H where x-0∈H = /ᴳ-effective p to .snd .Group-hom.pres-⋆ _ _ = Σ-prop-path (λ _ → H _ .is-tr) refl from : Groups.Hom _ _ from .fst (x , p) = x , quot (subst (_∈ H) (sym idr ∙ ap (_ ⋆_) (sym inv-unit)) p) from .snd .Group-hom.pres-⋆ _ _ = Σ-prop-path (λ _ → squash _ _) refl il = Forget-is-faithful $ funext λ x → Σ-prop-path (λ _ → H _ .is-tr) refl ir = Forget-is-faithful $ funext λ x → Σ-prop-path (λ _ → squash _ _) refl
To show that these are equal as subgroups of , we must show that the isomorphism above commutes with the inclusions; But this is immediate by computation, so we can conclude: Every normal subgroup is a kernel.
Ker[incl]≡H↪G : Ker-sg ≡ H-sg Ker[incl]≡H↪G = antisym ker≤H H≤ker where SubG = Subobjects (Groups ℓ) Groups-is-category Grp open Poset SubG open Groups._≅_ Ker[incl]≅H-group ker≤H : Ker-sg ≤ H-sg ker≤H ./-Hom.map = to ker≤H ./-Hom.commutes = Forget-is-faithful refl H≤ker : H-sg ≤ Ker-sg H≤ker ./-Hom.map = from H≤ker ./-Hom.commutes = Forget-is-faithful refl